[Crossposted at Family Scholars Blog]
In “What is Marriage?,” Girgis, George & Anderson (for convenience, I will refer to them as “George,” after their most senior member) argue that there is something called “true marriage” that exists apart from culture. But the truth is, huge numbers — probably the majority — of human cultures would not have agreed with George’s definition of “true marriage.” Many or most cultures have recognized polygyny or polyandry, for example. More recently, an increasing number of cultures recognize same-sex marriage. It’s extremely counter-intuitive to say that there is an objective, universally true definition of marriage which many or most human cultures have gotten wrong.
George writes:
Marriage’s independent reality is only confirmed by the fact that the known cultures of every time and place have seen fit to regulate the relationships of actual or would‐be parents to each other and to any children that they might have.
It seems dubious to claim “the known cultures of every time and place” to argue that marriage has an “independent reality,” while simultaneously defining “real marriage” in a way that contradicts how marriage was defined in many or most of those known cultures.
In my view, marriage is the institution by which people who aren’t each other’s immediate kin, become each other’s immediate kin. (This has the useful secondary effect of making two families, who may not have had previous connections, into kin.) Unlike George’s definition, my definition is accurate for the overwhelming majority of known human cultures, including — as far as I know — all present-day human cultures.
But although there is a core definition of marriage, shared by virtually all human cultures, there are also details which vary between cultures. So if I were defining marriage in the present-day US, I’d say it’s the institution by which two unmarried, consenting adults who are not close kin, become legally and socially recognized as each other’s immediate kin.
George argues that “revisionists” are unable to explain why incestuous marriages shouldn’t be legally recognized:
Many revisionists point out that there are important differences between these cases and same sex unions. Incest, for example, can produce children with health problems and may involve child abuse. But then, assuming for the moment that the state’s interest in avoiding such bad outcomes trumps what revisionists tend to describe as a fundamental right, why not allow incestuous marriages between adult infertile or same sex couples?
In my case, I’d first say that marriage is a kin-making institution, which by definition transforms two unrelated (or at least not closely related) people into close kin. It makes no more sense for marriage to turn close kin into close kin than it does for an alchemist to transform gold into gold. It’s already gold.
Second, I’d point out that limiting incestuous marriage to adults would not solve the problem of child abuse, and could conceivably make it worse. Legal recognition of incestuous marriage could give sexually abusive fathers (or mothers — but in most cases, sexually abusive parents are fathers) a strong incentive to sexually abuse their daughters, in hopes of crushing her will before she comes of age, so she’ll agree to marriage.
Finally, I’d argue that child health and child abuse are not the only harms of incest. Importantly, legalizing incestuous marriage between the infertile would transform currently existing families, by introducing the possibility of marriage into relationships that have never had that possibility. It fundamentally changes the relationship between father and son, or between sister and brother, if we add the possibility of marital union to those relationships.
A question often asked of SSM opponents — one they’ve never persuasively answered — is “how would your family be harmed if two women you don’t even know get married?” A traditional nuclear family in Massachusetts was no different after the Goodridge decision than before. But legalizing incestuous marriage would introduce new, intrusive and unwelcome possibilities into existing families, by making siblings, and even parents and children, evaluate each other not only as family members but also as potential mates and spouses.
* * *
Since there’s no evidence that same-sex marriage is harmful, SSM opponents commonly resort to a second-degree harm argument: We must not recognize SSM, because denying legal recognition to SSM is crucial for preventing incestuous marriage. (Or bestiality, or men marrying androids, and so on and so forth.) Although it’s unclear if George makes this precise argument, it’s a common argument among SSM opponents, and therefore worth addressing.
The implication of this argument is that legal recognition of SSM would necessarily (or at least plausibly) lead to the legal recognition of incestuous marriage.
But that’s not how change actually happens. Incestuous marriage will never be legally recognized in the US until millions of Americans become persuaded that it should be legally recognized. And there is no sign of that happening, because of SSM or for any other reason.
SSM opponents (particularly those less sophisticated than George) might respond that if the courts can recognize a right to SSM, then they could also force incestuous marriage down American’s collective throats, regardless of how disgusted Americans are by the prospect. But again, this argument shows a fundamental misunderstanding of how change happens. Judges do not create social change out of thin air; it is only in an atmosphere of commonplace (although not universal) acceptance of homosexuality that a court ruling had any practical power to bring about recognition of SSM.
In other words, legal incestuous marriage cannot happen until millions of Americans are persuaded to support it. The incestuous marriage objection to SSM therefore only makes sense if we assume that there are no persuasive arguments against incestuous marriage apart from banning SSM. But as we’ve already seen, that’s not the case.
But what if, as SSM opponents may believe, there are no persuasive arguments against incestuous marriage? Well, if there are no arguments against it, then why do we need to oppose incestuous marriage at all? More importantly, if there’s not a single persuasive argument against incestuous marriage, why believe that banning SSM will prevent incestuous marriage from ultimately being recognized?
Finally, consider the crucial issue of fairness. The argument that we must ban equal marriage for same-sex couples in order to prevent incestuous marriage treats LGBT people and their families instrumentally; it dehumanizes them by treating their lives and needs as if they are of no consequence, mere tools to be used (and if necessary destroyed) to prevent a bad policy outcome.
How have same-sex couples earned being punished for the sins of incestuous couples? Not in any way. What justifies singling out same-sex couples for this treatment? Nothing I’ve seen. Singling out same-sex couples for second class status in this way is unjust.
* * *
Related to this post, I’d encourage everyone to read the discussion of how George’s use of the word “discrimination” is slippery on the blog Waking Up Now.
Chairm, thanks so much for your participation. We appreciate your efforts.
However, I’m afraid, to quote Don Pedro, “This learned constable is too cunning to be understood.” For that reason, I’m afraid your visit to “Alas” has come to an end. Please do not post any more comments here.
Tell me if I’ve missed something. But isn’t the argument that there’s a slippery slope by which SSM will lead to polygamy, and the counter argument is that it doesn’t work like that as you can’t simply extend monogamous marriage law to encompass polygamy. I don’t see how drawing a distinction between polyamory and polygyny helps anyone here. People arguing for the slippery slope don’t think polygyny’s okay but polyamory crosses a line. And pointing out loads of places with traditions of monogamous marriage manage polygamy fine is perfectly relevant.
Sure, but there’s certainly law (at least in some places) on balancing obligations in these circumstances and making sure people aren’t shafted unfairly. The logic is that if I in good faith marry you and you’re already married, then our marriage may be null. But I don’t immediately lose all rights and get thrown in the gutter because you’re a bigamist and lied to me, the law should at least give me some protection because I entered into a ‘marriage’ I thought was legal and could rely upon.
No. People who approve of gay rights tend to be very supportive of polyamory – which makes sense, as they both grew from the sexual revolution and 60s counterculture. But polygyny is the sort of backward institution the counterculture was rebeling against, hell, its the sort of thing the culture was rebeling against.
Maybe it was unfair of me to bring this up. Counterculturals are sympathetic to Islam on an instinctive level because it’s non-western, and my enemies enemy is my friend. But the fact is traditional Islam isn’t particularly friendly to gays or liberal values – and as a consequence political advocates of gays and political advocates of islam really fucking hate each other. I don’t see that as controversial.
I don’t see how drawing a distinction between polyamory and polygyny helps anyone here.
The difference is a response to your counterargument, which is that it is too a slippery slope because somehow some governments manage to cope piecemeal with a handful of polygynous marriages legalized in other countries, therefore there must be some way to easy morph existing US law to address polyamorous marriage.
the law should at least give me some protection
Well, make up your mind, james. *Should* give or *does* give? And is the protection that you argue the law either should give or does give rise to the level of treating your non-marriage as the equivalent of a legal marriage? Because I’m not seeing how “the law should provide an innocent spouse a remedy if they are defrauded into thinking they are married” is proof that the law can easily accommodate and recognize multiple voluntary marriage.
Maybe it was unfair of me to bring this up.
I don’t know about unfair, but it was a little foolish of you to assert things as facts that you have absolutely no intention of supporting, or to assume that if you move your goalposts nobody will notice.
> marriage is the institution by which people who aren’t each other’s immediate kin, become each other’s immediate kin
I like the broadness of this definition, but I will note that it is broad enough to also include adoption.